Saturday, August 16, 2014

The Fortress of Metaethics: Reviews of Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other and Being Realistic about Reasons.




Metaethics is about what ethical claims mean, how they can be “justified,” and how ethical reasoning ought to be conducted.  Thomas Scanlon’s writing on metaethics has become a verbal icon for the enterprise. Scanlon now has two books elaborating his views, What We Owe to Each Other and Being Realistic about Reasons.  The first was reviewed with applause in literary venues where philosophy is seldom seen, and one can only expect the same of the second. Each book is a theoretical disappointment—no, the second is a disaster--the first from lacunae the second tries to fill, the second from the filling.[1]

In What We Owe to Each Other Scanlon’s stalking horse is utilitarianism. The many variants of utilitarianism share this much: they are voting theories, and so is Scanlon’s alternative, absent some key features. In utilitarianism, every sentient creature, or at least every human, has a stock of interests. Properly scaled, those are voting stocks. Anyone’s action predictably affects some of the interests, or the well-being, of some creatures. An action is permissible only if, among the alternative available actions, it maximizes some aggregate of the interests of all who may be affected by any of the available actions, so far as the actor can estimate.  That is the utilitarian schematic for how the affected stocks are to be weighed in moral assessment of action.  The specifics are contentious. How are pains and pleasures and sorrows and joys to be compared across persons, let alone persons and other animals, so that they can be aggregated?  That issue aside, suppose we have a number for each human state or well or mal being that takes account the diverse interests of each human being. Should one try to maximize the total, the average, the median well-being over all persons? Minimize the variance? Maximize something under a constraint (e.g., a bound on the variance, or the Difference Principle)? Count only changes to an individual’s interests that are above a certain threshold?  Order interests by type, higher type trumping lower, as one might read Mill to suggest? The utilitarian literature from Bentham on has this virtue: it takes these questions seriously and offers answers, not the same answers, of course. These are philosophers after all.

Scanlon’s theory is one piece of a different voting theory.  For any action one might do, the deliberator and others may have reasons, conscious or not, why it should or should not be done. The best of those reasons is decisive. Reasons are not to be aggregated; the best reason wins, no matter how few people have it. Which reasons count? Scanlon offers only this in general: We should seek to act only in accord with principles that other people could not reasonably reject if they too sought principles others could not reasonably reject.  A reason has moral bearing only if it is an application of such a principle.

One catch to Scanlon’s general schema for moral principles is “reasonably,” which in this context is particularly flabby. We have pretty clear notions of reasonable views in mathematics, less definite notions in science, but in ethics “unreasonable” is more a slur than a methodological complaint. Does Scanlon imagine a negotiation about which principles meet his criteria, or a social survey to find nearly universal principles (they would be few), or does he imagine principles that someone sincerely thinks others ought to share? In the latter case, utilitarian principles have a vote. No one thinks that the only reasons I can have for or against an action must be exclusively about me. Indeed, if by the proper weighting of principles and reasons utilitarian principles and reasons are the best, then Scanlon is committed to utilitarianism, one step back.

So what then are the principles of ordering of reasons or principles, and why? Scanlon does not say, only, examples aside, that the best reason wins, winner take all.  What then individuates reasons: if your action will impoverish me and cause me an illness besides, is that one reason or two? Scanlon doesn’t say, but in his voting scheme it matters.  The basic elements of the theory are unspecified: by what clear principles are reasons to be weighed, and why, what counts as a reason, how are reasons individuated? Almost all you might want in a theory is unspecified. One would not want election rules so vaguely posted.

The book has any number of appeals to quotidian examples where one would not consider global consequences, or global good, or aggregate harms and benefits. There are old saws: If a broadcasting engineer is painfully and continuously injured by continuing shock during the broadcast of a sports game—say Argentina versus Germany in the World Cup--and the only way to stop his agony is to interrupt the electric current that is necessary to broadcast the game, shouldn’t that be done—aren’t the enormous sum of annoyances to the passions of millions of soccer fans outweighed by the one engineer’s acute pain?  But what would be said in this kind of case by versions of utilitarianism in which what counts has thresholds, or versions in which there are layers of goods and bads that trump others? Should we not consider the number of people who might be killed in mad rages and riots were the television to go off in the midst of the game? In any case these examples can be bought cheap by either side. Being murdered is worse than not having children. If you met a person with a remarkably infectious, uncurable disease that renders all who catch it permanently sterile but is otherwise asymptomatic, and you could not capture him and isolate him before he spread it to the entire human population, would you kill him if you could?

If the aim is to articulate standards for correct norms, why trifle with mundane examples, unless one is doing moral sociology from an armchair? That question takes us to Scanlon’s more recent book, a defense of putting weight on such examples, and, more broadly, a defense of metaethics as a serious enterprise.  Scanlon does not fill all the gaps his first book left, but he addresses two major ones. The claims of Being Realistic about Reasons come down to these: there are true normative principles that are not just about the best means to ends, and there is a method for discovering them.  What is the argument?

Scanlon claims that there are various “domains” of inquiry. Each domain has its own standards for seeking the truth in its domain. Mathematics has its methods, empirical science has its methods, and, lo, normative matters, moral matters in particular, have theirs. One domain may not contradict, or, presumably, undermine, the methods and conclusions of another.  They are separate empires, contractually at peace. This last I call Scanlon’s Rule. He continues with implausible parallels between set theory (Scanlon was a logician in his youth) and normative reasoning.  Just as set theorists may debate and disagree about, say, Zorn’s Lemma, so metaethicists may debate and disagree fine points of the correct normative principles. Can one seriously think that the reasoning in ethics and metaethics has the rigor of mathematics? I can’t, and I doubt Scanlon does. Scanlon’s thesis is that they share the same style, the same form viewed with sufficient abstraction. So, with sufficient abstraction, do science and Cargo Cults.  The intellectual legitimacy of metaethics needs a better bolster.

The crucial point is Scanlon’s Rule. Scanlon’s Rule is pure defense, a paper wall to keep out critics. Mathematics and logic may be immune to contradiction from physics (although Hilary Putnam once thought otherwise, and presumably Mill would have allowed the possibility, and certainly the status of geometry has been altered by physics—and the status of metaethics is what is at stake here), but ethics is not immune to contradiction from other “domains.” Is religion a domain? Theological reasoning is more like metaethics than is set theory, and theology most definitely intrudes on ethics and on metaethics. Empirical science may not directly contradict normative claims, but it can surely undermine them. Once upon a time it was widely thought that there are particularly evil people, sorcerers and witches, who had made contracts with the most evil entity, Satan, and should be killed. Science has convinced the civilized that there are no witches and no sorcerers and no Satan. Once upon a time, it was thought that living beings have a superphysical constitution, that their chemicals are not the ordinary, “inorganic” stuff, and that living beings possess an unphysical “vital force” that guides evolution. Science has convinced us (Tom Nagel perhaps aside) otherwise. Science bids fair to do the same with the Will, and Autonomy, and Agency, and as, and if that more fully comes about, the idea of true, moral principles will go the way of true principles of witchcraft.

So what about the methods of ethics? Scanlon’s is “reflective equilibrium,” I think first proposed in Rawl’s essay “Outline of a decision procedure for ethics.”  Rawls imagined a panel of moral experts (much of his essay is about the qualifications for membership) who report on the moral statuses of sundry actions. The ethical theorist takes their pronouncements as data—putative moral facts—and attempts to form a general theory that accounts for them. Rawls allowed that on reflection one might reject a few of the experts’ decisions if accounting for them required excessive complexity in the theory, arbitrary exceptions and so on. The procedure came to be called “reflective equilibrium.”  That is Scanlon’s method, with the panel of experts replaced by one’s own judgements and the judgements of those whose ethical perspicuity one respects. His explanation of the reliability of its data sounds very much like Descartes “clear and distinct ideas”:

“In order for something to count as a considered judgment… It is necessary also that it should be something that seems to me to be clearly true when I am thinking about the matter under good conditions for arriving at judgments of the kind in question.”  Scanlon, T. M. (2014-01-06). Being Realistic about Reasons (p. 82). Oxford University Press, USA. Kindle Edition.   (Italics are Scanlon’s)

I have no doubt that some very thoughtful people, no doubt Scanlon himself, form their moral views in this way. I even think it’s a good way. But I have no doubt, either, that in many other “domains” something similar is often followed. It is general and vague enough to characterize both the process of Islamic jurisprudence and the quasi Bayesian process often at work in science in which data are thought to come with probabilities of error and the sufficiently low posterior of a datum conditional on a hypothesis of sufficiently high probability is reason to reject the datum, or even to reject an entire set of measurements. But these examples are exactly the problem.  In Bayesian statistics one can prove that under specified, general assumptions, application of Bayes rule converges to the truth. One can do the same for modifications, perhaps even considered variants of the one I suggest off-hand above. In statistical estimation and machine learning (the latter of which Rawls, in keeping with the opinion of his time, announced was impossible) proofs are given that under very general assumptions search methods converge on the truth, and methods are provided for testing the assumptions. Nothing like that can be done for Islamic jurisprudence, and nothing like that can be done for Rawl’s decision procedure for ethics or Scanlon’s variant. That one can apply a vaguely specified procedure in a domain is no argument, no evidence, that the procedure finds the truth in that domain, or that there is any truth there to be found.  

The least attention to the world shows that the range of considered moral judgements is incompatible with any unified theory of morality.  Scanlon will have to discard many of the moral judgements of most people in the world. He should, but he should not claim that in doing so he is exercising a method for finding truth. Scanlon has only two responses. Those who want to (and do) crucify Christians and behead Jewish journalists and do other atrocities are not in “good conditions” for such judgements;  and that ethics and metaethics have their own standards for concluding what is true--outside standards and alien practices, however common, are irrelevant. 

There is plenty of work for metaethics to do: systematizing vague strategies of inference—Nozick’s efforts were a good start[i]--finding and recognizing contradictions, figuring out how principles apply in morally difficult cases, contrasting misweighings of moral importance, finding agreements and disagreements in clarified moral perspectives, tempering ethical demands to human capacities, and so on, all without Scanlon’s truth claims. Scanlon’s redoubt is a parochial fortress, impenetrable to the forces of science or to the objections of the world outside and its domains.




[1] I write this and what follows with some regret, since Scanlon was my closest friend when we were colleagues. This blog may lose me a lot of friends.


[i] Nozick, Robert, "Moral Complications and Moral Structures" (1968). Natural Law Forum. Paper 137.
http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum/137

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.